Lade Inhalt...

Mathematics and Beauty

An Attempt to Link the Cognitive and Philosophical-Spiritual Aspects of Beauty

von Andrej Démuth (Autor:in) Slávka Démuthová (Autor:in) Adrián Slavkovský (Autor:in)
Monographie 160 Seiten
Reihe: Spectrum Slovakia, Band 30

Zusammenfassung

The monograph outlines the dual role of mathematics in relation to beauty. On one hand mathematics refers to an objective, through mathematical formulas expressible side of beauty. On the other hand, it points out that entirely abstract things like mathematical equations can be seen as beautiful, too. This refers to two aspects of beauty. 1. The biological, evolutionary: our brains react to certain aesthetic stimuli in scientifically adequately explainable way. 2. Philosophical spiritual: This shows a connection of beauty with goodness and being. To such a perception we can mature. Handed down wisdom can be mentioned as a hint: You cannot find beauty, if you don’t carry it in yourself. Such an analysis can help us understand why we use the word beauty in so many different ways.

Inhaltsverzeichnis

  • Cover
  • Title
  • Copyright
  • About the authors
  • About the book
  • Contents
  • 1. Introduction – Let None but the Geometric Enter Here
  • 2. Mathematics as Seeking Symmetry
  • 2.1. Trivial and Non-trivial Proofs
  • 2.2. Symmetry
  • 2.2.1. The Attractiveness of Symmetry
  • 2.2.2. Symmetry in Mathematics
  • 2.3. Knowledge – the Metaphor of Symmetry
  • 3. Beauty as a Calculation
  • 3.1. Computational Aesthetics
  • 3.2. Perception as a Calculation
  • 3.3. Beauty as a Calculation with an Unclear Solution Algorithm
  • 3.3.1. Calculations of the Beauty of Human Faces
  • 3.3.1.1. The History of the Examination of Facial Parameters
  • 3.3.1.2. Applying the Golden Ratio
  • 3.3.1.3. Applying the Idea of the Average
  • 3.3.1.4. Applying the Idea of Symmetry
  • 3.3.1.5. Contemporary Research into Beautiful Face
  • 3.3.2. Ideal and Composite Image
  • 3.3.3. Taste and the Calculation of Average Values for Opinions
  • 3.3.4. Aesthetic Value and the Calculation of Rewards
  • 3.4. Preliminary Summary
  • 4. Philosophical Questions Associated with the Mathematics of Beauty
  • 4.1. The Metaphysical Status of Beauty
  • 4.2. Why Do We Mathematicize?
  • 4.3. Why Do We Perceive Beauty?
  • 4.4. Biological Sources of Mathematical and Artistic Beauty
  • 4.5 The Metaphysical Meaning of Beauty
  • 5. Learning to Perceive
  • 5.1. The Beauty of Mathematical Tricks
  • 5.2. Are Mathematical Ideas Some of the Most Transformative and Beautiful in History?
  • 5.3. Developments in Mathematics, the Transcendence of Previous Levels and Beauty
  • 5.4. Disputes in Mathematics
  • 5.5. Fascinated by Ideas
  • 6. Conclusions
  • 7. References
  • 8. About Authors
  • Series index

←6 | 7→

1. Introduction – Let None but the Geometric Enter Here

Andrej Démuth,

Slávka Démuthová,

Adrián Slavkovský

←7 |
 8→

←8 | 9→

In his book Úhelný kámen evropské vzdělanosti a moci (The Cornerstone of European Scholarship and Power) (Vopěnka 2001, 53), Petr Vopěnka expressed his belief that it was not the desire for truth, but rather awe and beauty, which led ancient philosophers to an interest in theoretical knowledge. Knowledge would be acquired regardless, by the common utilization of objects or by word of mouth,1 but an interest in knowledge for its own sake is what separates a barbaric approach to knowledge to that of the ancient philosophers. A barbarian (whatever interpretation of this word we choose to use) does not observe the world for the world itself. He is only interested in survival, in fulfilling his goals, desires and needs; and knowledge is only one of the means to achieve these ends. That is why he does not hesitate to use objects for purposes other than those which they were made for – he does not find it necessary to learn why a thing is as it is, how it is linked to its history, being, etc. The only relevant aspect of it is whether it meets his needs. Ancient thinkers, however, observed things for different reasons. They were interested in the things themselves, in their nature, laws, being. A pre-eminent example of this is the concept of theory, which is the centrepiece of the Greek understanding of the meaning and nature of knowledge.

The term theory means “viewing”, “beholding”. In his On the Soul, Aristotle adds that it always pertains to observation, speculation, but also contemplation – the highest form of philosophical activity (Aristotle 1996). However, theory is not an observation focused on finding a secondary purpose or personal gain. On the contrary, it is characterized by an interest in a thing for the thing itself. We study it not so we can better manipulate it or to achieve certain goals, but because the thing and its being interests us.2 To be able to study it well, however, as Martin Heidegger (Heidegger 1995, 165) points out, we need sufficient time. Theoretical observations are therefore characterized by us having the time and desire to observe, view, behold, imagine, speculate and test things both hypothetically and in reality – to occupy ourselves with them, to get to know them better. The value of such activity dwells in the finding itself, not in any further use of it. That is what theory and the Greek notion of knowledge have in common with beauty.

←9 | 10→

For many philosophers, beauty does not have any individual function, except for occupying our minds and forcing us to perceive. The purpose of beautiful objects is to be, and if they were created as works of art, maybe also to be liked. Beauty is thus not something that would stop a barbarian. A barbarian does not recognize beauty. Specifically, he has no time for it. His worldview does not take it into account, similar to knowledge for the sake of knowledge.

One of the spaces where beauty meets knowledge is mathematics. In this book we will attempt to illustrate that what we find alluring in mathematics often has much in common with beauty, and, vice versa, that beauty is, as it were, a mathematical entity, or is often linked to mathematical operations, calculations and that its characteristic traits can be expressed through mathematical analysis. We will also try to show that just as mathematics is not an eminently theoretical discipline without any real impact on the world and our practical actions, so is beauty, though apparently entirely purposeless, not just a pleasant feeling, but that the perception of beauty is principally contaminated by epistemic content and has a deeper function than is obvious at first glance. The object of the following reflections will therefore not only be the relationship between mathematics and beauty (what makes mathematics attractive, what are the characteristics of mathematic beauty and what do mathematics and beauty have in common), but also to what extent can we analyse beauty mathematically and whether we carry out any calculations in perceiving beauty, what is the metaphysical status of mathematical and beautiful objects and so on.


1 Builders in ancient Mesopotamia and Egypt used strings in their work long before the birth of geometry and solved their daily tasks without any knowledge of theoretical laws.

2 Aristotle distinguishes between theory and episteme (understanding – De an, II 1: Met. VIII, 6., Phys. VII 3, EN VII 5). Knowing has a certain episteme and uses it – realizes it (I know because I know that...). In contrast, techne is a process of crafting, from the very beginning focused on the given goal – function.

←10 | 11→

2. Mathematics as Seeking Symmetry

←11 |
 12→

←12 | 13→

Mathematics is among the oldest disciplines of human knowledge and has developed independently everywhere where there is evidence of human culture.3 It not only includes simple calculations, but also the investigation of the laws of quantity, structure, space and change and in its observations leans on both visual thinking (geometry) and abstract thinking. Mathematicians (gr. μαθηματικός (mathematikós) from μάθημα (máthēma), “knowledge”) – scholars – were thus people who not only knew something, but (according to Aristotle’s claim from the Posterior Analytics) also knew the “why”. Their knowledge did not come purely from a need for solutions to real issues, but from the results of theoretical exercises and a purely theoretical interest in the object of observation and the relationships between individual objects. That may be the reason why ancient scholars often eventually found the objects they were interested in outside of the common material world. Pythagoreans understood numbers as divine entities and did not see geometric objects as bound to the inventory of the material-burdened world. A geometrical triangle is not one that you trace with a finger in the sand, nor is it the one carved in stone. The triangle of which we can speak is the one in the ideal – geometrical world. The worlds of geometry and algebra cannot be plumbed by one’s own eyes. The line you can see is never perfectly straight, infinite and single-dimensional. What you perceive is just a material, imperfect simulacrum. “True” geometrically straight lines only exist in the world of ideas.

No surprise then, that Platonic philosophy is so well received among mathematicians. Its essence is the world of ideas. Truth, if it is to be, in fact, true, needs to apply to something eternal, infinite, immutable, something that can be known without fear that in a few moments that knowledge will no longer be true (Démuth 2013b). That is something the material world simply cannot offer. Entering the world of truths is therefore entering the spaces “beyond the world”4 – it is the art of finding the signs and archetypes of something eternal and divine in this world – of something, which ←13 | 14→is true. The ability to see the eternal contents is not always entirely natural and innate. It is often the case that a person needs to be initiated to allow them to see otherworldly objects.5

One of the classical examples of the initiation of a candidate to knowledge of science is education. As Petr Vopěnka (Vopěnka 2001, 34) suggests, teaching mathematics is about demonstrating facts and their evidence. A teacher can only demonstrate using examples, by means of which he reveals the given knowledge, but the pupil must see the knowledge by himself in the examples. It is therefore not irrelevant which roads are taken to knowledge, which roads do our thoughts travel. Sometimes, in demonstrating the mathematical world, the road of thought itself – the method of thinking – is beautiful, because by understanding it the pupil attains a tool that can reveal other – new (hitherto unknown) content. On such a road, one may encounter many remarkable, unexpected and alluring objects, or not – the road only being a tedious sequence of necessary steps. Sometimes, there are multiple roads to the result,6 and the choice of some of them may be more confusing than enlightening for a candidate. In such cases, a student does not perceive the laws, nor does he fully understand how he got to where he is and what it is that he perceives. He is but the silent witness to a spectacle he does not comprehend. If a candidate does not see the revelation of truth, he only perceives the demonstrated examples and does not understand. In contrast, if he understands why, the route his mind must follow and where his teacher is taking him, he will understand not only the laws and the beauty of the road, but will also see the ideas revealed in their own world and understand them. The Evidence of these relationships is often clear and self-evident and therefore do not need any further proof.7 Some basic proofs are entirely natural and do not need any hints. Some only appear after we are shown, or after the road we need to take to see them is suggested to us.

Details

Seiten
160
ISBN (PDF)
9783631794890
ISBN (ePUB)
9783631794906
ISBN (MOBI)
9783631794913
ISBN (Hardcover)
9783631794883
Sprache
Deutsch
Erscheinungsdatum
2019 (Oktober)
Schlagworte
Philosophy Psychology Aesthetics Neuroaesthetics Epistemology
Erschienen
Berlin, Bern, Bruxelles, New York, Oxford, Warszawa, Wien. 2019, 160 S., 2 Tab.

Biographische Angaben

Andrej Démuth (Autor:in) Slávka Démuthová (Autor:in) Adrián Slavkovský (Autor:in)

Andrej Démuth is a Professor of philosophy at the Comenius University in Bratislava. Slávka Démuthová is an Associate Professor and the Head of the Department of Psychology at the Faculty of Arts, University of Ss. Cyril and Methodius in Trnava. Adrián Slavkovský is an Associate Professor at the Department of Philosophy at Trnava University.

Zurück

Titel: Mathematics and Beauty
book preview page numper 1
book preview page numper 2
book preview page numper 3
book preview page numper 4
book preview page numper 5
book preview page numper 6
book preview page numper 7
book preview page numper 8
book preview page numper 9
book preview page numper 10
book preview page numper 11
book preview page numper 12
book preview page numper 13
book preview page numper 14
book preview page numper 15
book preview page numper 16
book preview page numper 17
book preview page numper 18
book preview page numper 19
book preview page numper 20
book preview page numper 21
book preview page numper 22
book preview page numper 23
book preview page numper 24
book preview page numper 25
book preview page numper 26
book preview page numper 27
book preview page numper 28
book preview page numper 29
book preview page numper 30
book preview page numper 31
book preview page numper 32
162 Seiten