Loading...

Democracy, Legal Education and the Political

by Michał Paździora (Volume editor) Michał Stambulski (Volume editor)
Edited Collection 188 Pages

Summary

The articles collected in the book present a view of legal education in Central and Eastern Europe, considering the relationship between democracy and the Political. In this perspective, legal education is a forum for this articulation and an area for a discursive search for solutions. On the one hand, democracy is a continuous object of research for the legal academia; legal theorists and constitutionalists debate the juridical foundations of modern constitutionalism, democracy and the rule of law. On the other hand, as university teachers, legal academics contribute to shaping future lawyer-citizens by instilling in them a certain vision of civic virtues and democratic values.

Table Of Contents

  • Cover
  • Title
  • Copyright
  • About the author
  • About the book
  • This eBook can be cited
  • Contents
  • Introduction
  • Experience and Community of Sense in Legal Education: A Pragmatic Approach (Michał Paździora)
  • Education and Democratic Values from the Transitional Justice Perspective (Michał Krotoszyński)
  • Post-Communist Legal Education? (Filip Cyuńczyk)
  • Hierarchies and Authority in Legal Education: Contesting Professorial Power (Michał Stambulski)
  • Discourse of the Master, Discourse of the University: An Archaeology of Modern Legal Education in Romania (Cosmin Sebatian Cercel)
  • Law Schools Between Autonomy and Democracy: The Case of Romanian Legal Academia (Alexandra Mercescu)
  • Coronavirus at the Faculty of Law, McGill University: The Long and Winding Road to Remote Pedagogy (Mirosław Michał Sadowski)
  • Legal Education in Croatia: The Influence of Integral Theory of Law (Marin Keršić)
  • Interdisciplinary Research on the Judiciary in Hungary (Edina Vinnai)
  • When and How Can Linguistic Comparison Help to Interpret the EU Legislation? (Karolina Paluszek)
  • Current Issues in the Relation Between Legislation and Administrative Punishment (Matej Horvat)
  • List of Contributors
  • Series Index

←6 | 7→

Introduction

The texts included in this volume are linked to the 9th Central and Eastern European Forum of Young Legal, Political and Social Theorists (CEE Forum) which was organised in 2017 in Wroclaw under the title “Democracy, Academia and the Political.” The aim this volume is to examine the role of legal education in democracy, with particular regard to the political (das Politische, le politique) which we understand as the inalienable antagonism which is at the basis of every society.

The presented texts are based on the premise that mutual relation between the democracy and legal education are complex and overlapping. Democracy is a type of political regime with distinct institutions which helps to articulate and tame antagonisms. In this perspective, the legal education is a forum for this articulation and an area for discursive search for the solutions. On the one hand, democracy is a continuous object of research for the legal academia; legal theorists and constitutionalists engage in debates on the juridical foundations of modern constitutionalism, democracy and the rule of law. On the other hand, legal academics – in their capacity as university teachers – contribute to shaping future lawyers-citizens by instilling in them a certain vision of civic virtues and democratic values. More broadly, world of democratic politics has a tangible influence on how the academia functions, not least through laying down the legal framework on the organisation of universities, conferral of academic degrees, requirements regarding academic education, as well as by a conscious grant policy. These broad phenomena, which academics are perfectly aware of and experience in everyday professional life, have not, however, been hitherto sufficiently theorised, especially in and with regard to region of Central and Eastern Europe, especially within the context of the crisis of legal authority and democratic representation, the rise of populism, emerging questions regarding the application of the “rule of law” principle in practice, the role of the legal education and academia in the social and political transformations. The authors of each chapter hope to contribute to those discussions.

←8 | 9→

Michał Paździora

Experience and Community of Sense in Legal Education: A Pragmatic Approach

Abstract: Anti-foundationalism rejects philosophy’s traditional striving for the certitude of our cognition which used to be based on durable, unquestioned foundations. Accepting the thesis that such foundations are neither available nor necessary for human knowledge and social practices, this does not necessarily imply that we are abandoning the hope of obtaining a universal validity of claims that are made. Therefore, that there is a need to seek a new source of validation which allows reconciling the fact of plurality of views and values, on the one hand, and the normative claims to universality, on the other hand. The philosophy of pragmatism is perfect for this task in legal education. For pragmatists, the experience is habit formation, and habit formation is a mode of cognition. The article aims to show that using examples of hard cases in legal education we train more than just legal reasoning skills. We create a community of sense (sensus communis), an intersubjective community which is the source of validation of potential judgments. In order to communicate our judgments and solutions, we need to respect different ways of perceiving the world and inscribe our judgments into different perspectives, communicating them in a way that is comprehensible to others. The faculty of judgment can be reduced to the requirement of raising oneself above the ‘subjective conditions of an individual judgment’ by the capacity of taking note of other perspectives and making an attempt at situating oneself within those perspectives.

Keywords: legal education, hard cases, aesthetic of law, anti-foundationalism, the political

Introduction

In contemporary philosophy of law we can observe increasingly more visible anti-foundationalist tendencies, which creates a need to find a new basis for the validation of judgments. Anti-foundationalism rejects philosophy’s traditional striving for certitude of our cognition which used to be based on durable, unquestioned foundations.

Anti-foundationalism teaches that questions of fact, truth, correctness, validity, and clarity can neither be posed nor answered in reference to some extracontextual, ahistorical, nonsituated reality, or rule, or law, or value; rather, anti- foundationalism asserts, all these matters are intelligible and debatable only within the precincts of the contexts or situations or paradigms or communities that give them their local and change able shape. (Fish 1989: 344)

←9 | 10→

Accepting the thesis that such foundations are neither available, nor necessary for human knowledge and for social practices, this does not necessarily imply that we are abandoning the hope of obtaining a universal validity of claims that are made. Therefore, that there is a need to seek a new source of validation which allows to reconcile the fact of plurality of views and values, on the one hand, and the normative claims to universality, on the other hand.

To this purpose, I will present a method based on hard cases in legal education. For pragmatists, the problematic situation is the beginning of cognition. Legal interpretation in hard cases is not only about removing doubts related to the indeterminate meaning of a legal text. Focusing on hard cases in legal education, we learn that the questions we ask and the goals we pursue in the process of making judgments are, in part, a function of the practice we participate.

1. Philosophical perspectives

Following the linguistic turn, the central problem of philosophy is answering the question regarding the possibility of speaking of universal validity in a world, in which human thought and action have irrevocably lost their metaphysical foundations. According to Habermas, modernity is a feature of times in which we are living – without reference to any specific period. It is a situation (structure) in which individuals and societies find themselves in their historicity.

Modernity can and will no longer borrow the criteria by which it takes its orientation from the models supplied by another epoch; it has to create its normativity out of itself. Modernity sees itself cast back upon itself without any possibility of escape (Habermas 2007: 5).

In other words, they gain a historical consciousness of themselves and their own actions. This consciousness allows them to understand their own times and coordinate their actions directed at the future, thereby rejecting an uncritical acceptance of directives following from tradition. The sense of responsibility depends, therefore, on historically perceived freedom. The ‘novelty of modernity,’ this originality of times in which we live, rests upon the self-consciousness of our own historicity, our moral choices and our institutional solutions. It is an epoch in which we must accept responsibility for the normative systems which we have created ourselves. The irreversibility of changes brought about by modernity can be illustrated by the principle of modern subjectivity. Substantially understood reason is replaced by reason whose unity has a merely formal character. The Kantian separation of the reason into formally connected moments gives birth to three autonomous spheres of judgment, typical for modernity: truth, ←10 | 11→morality and aesthetics. Nonetheless, such judgments can no longer be guaranteed by a metaphysical vision of the world, nor can they be legitimised by a tradition which should be protected and cherished. From now on, the questions put forward by Kant: “What can I know?,” “What should I do?,” and “What can I hope?” (Kant 2009: 677 A805/B833), have a strictly anthropological grounding. These questions reflect the ontological instability of the ‘modern’ individual, whose subjectivity is torn between, on the one hand, the subject’s autonomy, and, on the other hand, the subject’s need for recognition by others. The irreversibility of changes leads to an inescapable tension between ‘what is’ and ‘what ought to be.’ For the supporters of the idea of modernity, this internal tension is an experience constitutive for our times, liberating in individuals the force constantly to transcend beyond visions of the world they have been born into, to create ever more perfect solutions and institutions. Conversely, for the critics of modernity, this constant tension resembles a situation of neurosis, in which commands originating from childhood prove to be outdated, dust-covered schemata, the destruction of which leads to a longing for an irreversibly lost security. The models of justification present in the philosophy of law, in order to support the generality and universality of adopted solutions, are based on a dichotomous opposition between “what is” (legal positivism, legal realism) and “what ought to be” (natural law). The few theories which make a programmatic attempt at eliminating this dichotomy also continuously stumble upon accusations of foundationalism, which they are unable to rebut (J. Habermas’s discursive theory of law, R. Dworkin’s philosophy of law as integrity), whilst theories which programmatically reject any form of foundationalism are accused of relativism and interpretive anarchism. According to Alessandro Ferrara, today, following the linguistic turn which has come to dominate contemporary philosophy, we feel even more the pressing need of securing a universal form of justification of proposals and institutional solutions which would not be based on discredited discourses: that of legal positivism or natural law (Ferrara 2008). This need, although it is broadly discussed both in political and legal discourse, should also be clearly put forward within the discourse of legal philosophy. For Ferrara and other philosophers who treat the linguistic turn seriously, it is clear that we do not have a direct access to reality and what is the object of our cognition are exclusively discourses which tell us more about ourselves. We have to become conscious of the fact that understanding or interpretation does not consist in the need to apply theory, but is always a question of a specific practice. Of course, practice does not consist exclusively of practical actions but also encompasses what William James refers to as the whole of human life, including everything that such life is composed of: emotions, intellectual passions, as well as moral needs (James 1907: 92). The ←11 | 12→language of law and the language of lawyers are also built around one rule which could be described and explained only by theory, and the relation between language and the world has no logical mapping.

1.1 Towards aesthetics

Ferrara tries to point to the third possibility of validation which can be deduced from H. Arendt’s interpretation of Kant’s Critique of the Faculty of Judgment. According to Arendt, the most striking aspect of Kant’s analyses made in his third critique is the unequivocal privileging of the question of taste: the sensus communis, the faculty of judgment and the differentiation between good and evil are all based on the sense of taste. (Arendt 1990) The superior role of the sense of taste follows especially from the fact that taste, is not concerned with objects of representation but refers exclusively to the subjective method of making them present in imagination. Just as the self is part of a community, the aesthetic judgment is part of a community of imagination. The fact that we want to communicate about our aesthetic judgments makes us think about others. We think about how other individuals make use of their imagination. In this way, aesthetic judgments show us why we are social beings (Arendt source). The intersubjective validity of aesthetic judgments is not only about representing absent objects. Imagination also helps to create images or patterns that help assess the events and behaviour of others. It helps to distinguish good and bad judgments by imagining concrete examples. Imagination, therefore, allows us to free ourselves from individual circumstances and achieve relative impartiality. The confrontation between the individual and others to which the individual turns to, is based on a game of imagination. It is due to imagination that the confrontation, which takes place within the judgment of taste, is not so much a discussion about actual aesthetic judgments, but rather a discussion on the very possibility of such judgments.

Instead, we must [here] take sensus communis to mean the idea of a sense shared [by all of us],i.e., a power to judge that in reflecting takes account (a priori), in our thought, of everyone else’s way of presenting [something], in order as it were to compare our own judgment with human reason in general and thus escape the illusion that arises from the ease of mistaking subjective and private conditions for objective ones, an illusion that would have a prejudicial influence on the judgment. (Kant 1987: 160)

The idea of a sensus communis in which all people participate is, according to Kant, a community of imagination which precedes any conceptual descriptions. The confrontation of an individual’s own judgments with the judgments of other individuals becomes the condition of the intersubjective comprehensibility of ←12 | 13→our enunciations. Should this possibility of confrontation not be available, our enunciations would become incomprehensible, they would cease to be judgments which are pronounced with regard to things available to others. In the case of an aesthetic judgment, we proceed from the singular towards the universal, and not from the universal towards the singular. The freedom of imagination reveals itself in a non-hierarchical game, a game free from any theoretical or practical determination by some specific conceptual content. It is characterised, above all, by the impossibility of using any concepts available a priori in the objective sense. In order to communicate our judgments and solutions, we need to respect different ways of perceiving the world and inscribe our judgments into different perspectives, communicating them in a way that is comprehensible to others. The faculty of judgment can be reduced to the requirement of raising oneself above the ‘subjective conditions of an individual judgment’ by the capacity of taking note of other perspectives and making an attempt at situating oneself within those perspectives.

1.2 Experience and a community of sense

Basing the faculty of judgment upon the condition of the universal validity of aesthetic judgments leads to the concepts of sensus communis and experience.

Table 1. Attributes of judgment

Judgment of truth

Details

Pages
188
ISBN (PDF)
9783631894385
ISBN (ePUB)
9783631894392
ISBN (Hardcover)
9783631871041
DOI
10.3726/b20458
Language
English
Publication date
2022 (December)
Keywords
Legal Education Democracy The Political Civil Society Legal Professions
Published
Berlin, Bern, Bruxelles, New York, Oxford, Warszawa, Wien, 2023. 188 pp., 2 tables

Biographical notes

Michał Paździora (Volume editor) Michał Stambulski (Volume editor)

Dr. Michał Paździora is an assistant professor at the University of Wrocław. Poland. He publishes articles on legal theory, legal education and philosophy of law. Michal Stambulski is assistant professor at the Erasmus School of Law at the University of Wroclaw. Poland. He publishes articles on legal theory, philosophy of politics and constitutionalism, and legal education.

Previous

Title: Democracy, Legal Education and the Political
book preview page numper 1
book preview page numper 2
book preview page numper 3
book preview page numper 4
book preview page numper 5
book preview page numper 6
book preview page numper 7
book preview page numper 8
book preview page numper 9
book preview page numper 10
book preview page numper 11
book preview page numper 12
book preview page numper 13
book preview page numper 14
book preview page numper 15
book preview page numper 16
book preview page numper 17
book preview page numper 18
book preview page numper 19
book preview page numper 20
book preview page numper 21
book preview page numper 22
book preview page numper 23
book preview page numper 24
book preview page numper 25
book preview page numper 26
book preview page numper 27
book preview page numper 28
book preview page numper 29
book preview page numper 30
book preview page numper 31
book preview page numper 32
book preview page numper 33
book preview page numper 34
book preview page numper 35
book preview page numper 36
book preview page numper 37
book preview page numper 38
189 pages