Loading...

Re-thinking the Angelic Doctor

W. Norris Clarke and the Concept of Person in Thomas Aquinas

by Aloysius N. Ezeoba (Author)
©2023 Monographs XII, 292 Pages

Summary

Re-thinking the Angelic Doctor is a major new reassessment of the reception of Thomas Aquinas in the work of the twentieth-century American philosopher W. Norris Clarke. Author Aloysius N. Ezeoba explores the question of whether Clarke was engaged in a "creative retrieval" of Aquinas’ system of thought – with a focus on the human person – or whether Clarke was forging his own path in attemptting to provide a "creative completion". Shedding new light on the workings of two great minds separated by eight centuries, Re-thinking the Angelic Doctor will be of interest to readers who are looking for a timely re-examination of the Aristotelian arguments, especially as they are appropriated by template religious thinkers such as Aquinas. It will also be a valuable resource in graduate courses in medieval and modern philosophy and theology.

Readers concerned with understanding how to appropriate St. Thomas Aquinas’s thinking for the twenty-first century will be greatly assisted in this task by reflecting upon this volume. They will learn much about the last century’s attempts to rethink St. Thomas from the varied positions of neo-Thomists in movements such as Transcendental and Existential Thomism. They will understand the ways in which thinkers such as Marechal and Phelan, were recrafting or, perhaps, abandoning classical Thomism, and how contemporary thinkers, such as Rev. Christopher Cullen, S.J. were countering with arguments defending traditional Thomism. And, importantly, they will confront the thought of one important figure connected with this appropriation: Rev. Norris W. Clarke, S.J., with whom I had contact in many ways as a fellow faculty member and as a popular lecturer. This book is an analytically precise, thoughtful, fruitful exercise in philosophy. It renders appropriate homage to that important twentieth-century Jesuit philosopher and teacher, and prepares the ground for critical appraisal of other various creative appropriations of St. Thomas Aquinas in the past century.
—William P. Baumgarth, Sr., PhD, Associate Professor of Political Philosophy, Fordham University.

Table Of Contents

  • Cover
  • Title
  • Copyright
  • About the author
  • About the book
  • This eBook can be cited
  • Contents
  • Foreword
  • Introduction
  • Part I Human Person as Substance
  • 1 The Human Person in Clarke is a Dynamic Substance Rooted in Esse
  • 2 Human Substance in Aquinas’ vis-à-vis Clarke’s
  • 3 Clarke’s Problem with The Human Substance Among Some Modern and Contemporary Thinkers
  • 4 New Notion of Substance as Intrinsically Dynamic
  • Part II Human Person as Relation
  • 1 Clarke’s Theory of Relation in Aquinas
  • 2 The Origin of The Primordial Notion of Relations
  • 3 Developed Primordial Relations Among Contemporary Thinkers
  • 4 Clarke and Contentious Problems of Person as Relation in the Contemporary Thought
  • Part III Human Person as Substance-in-Relation
  • 1 Clarke’s Notion of Person
  • 2 Reason for Relation (agere)
  • 3 The Ontological Orientation of the Human Person
  • 4 Transcendental Method
  • Part IV Aquinas’ Root of Clarke’s Thought and Relational Problem
  • 1 Substance-in-relation: Creative Retrieval or Completion of Aquinas’ Thought?
  • 2 Relational Problem, Dangers, and Proposal
  • 3 Proposal for the Development of the Primordial Relation in esse
  • Conclusion
  • Bibliography
  • Index

←viii | ix→

Foreword

Generally, neo-Thomism refers to neo-scholastic philosophy or theory concerned with the teachings of Thomas Aquinas. It is the application of the teachings of St. Thomas to the development of thought in both the modern and contemporary eras. An ancient usage (indicated by some as improperly) referred to the revival of interest in Aquinas in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries as inspired by the writings of Cajetan.

More accurately, neo-Thomism refers to the revival after Vatican 1, which was prompted by the issuance of Aeterni Patris (Encyclical of Pope Leo XIII on the Restoration of Christian Philosophy) on August 4, 1879. One approach has been to emphasize the opinions of Aquinas commentators, explicating and systematizing these. Another and more influential has been to abandon the scholastic method in favor of reformulating Aquinas’ thought in more discursive and historical ways. Notable exponents of this later approach have been Jacques Mauritian and Etienne Gilson. Both approaches have shared Aquinas’ point of departure that reason can know that God exists, but that revelation is needed to understand what God is. Neo-Thomism is also sometimes applied to those more commonly known as Transcendental Thomists. Notable exponents have been Bernard Lonergan and Karl Rahner.

←ix | x→

We work with what we earlier regarded as a more accurate appellation of neo-Thomism. The desire to correctly interpret Aeterni Patris led to serious academic disputes or even quarrels among outstanding Thomists in the Catholic Universities of the time. The question was: what does the revival of Thomism concretely mean? Two medieval Schools of Thought gave different answers to the question. On the one hand, one school saw it as an undiluted exposition of the teachings of the angelic doctor as contained in his writings. The other disagreed by maintaining that it is to find ways of making the teaching of Thomas relevant to and valuable for resolving some of the era’s problems. The disagreement between the two schools generated heated debates and academic differences. It is not our business in this write-up to go into the details. Suffice it to say that the work accomplished by Dr. Ezeoba followed the second approach – that the teachings of Thomas could be relevant both to thinkers of every era and resolution of related problems.

The work is the interpretation of an interpretation. It is a re-thinking of the thinking of a known neo-Thomist, Norris W. Clarke, on the Conception of the Person in Thomas Aquinas. Starting with Aquinas’ concept of the human person as a substance composed of body and soul, he goes on to apply the notion of the “Other.” That is, the human substance does not exist alone; there are others. Man is not simply a substance; he is “substance-in-relation” in relation with others. Dr. Ezeoba considers this approach to be a retrieval and completion of the thought of Aquinas. I add, a creative completion. Clarke thereby completes the thought of Aquinas using well-known relational notions developed by existential and phenomenological philosophers. Outstanding here is the notion that human substance is intrinsically relational. This assertion emanates from “Aquinas discussion on esse,” which “indicates that esse is intrinsically dynamic and it is this intrinsic dynamism that gives it the inner drive to diffuse itself to others.”

This leads us to Dr. Ezeoba’s unique contribution. He does not stop at Clark’s “we are,” which he treated in considerable detail. He goes a step further with his unique notion of “1-We,” which “enables the human person to see oneself in others and to see others in oneself.” He acknowledges the earlier contributions of thinkers before him, such as Martin Buber’s “I-Thou.” We add Martin Heidegger’s “being-with,” Alfred Schutz’s “We-relation,” and Ifeanyi Nnoruka’s “People-Coming-Together.” Dr. Ezeoba’s “I-We” is undeniably unique. He identifies it with “the seat of compassion in the human person,” which has a reciprocal dimension, “in giving, one is receiving, and in receiving, one is also giving.” It follows that the ontological characteristics of the I-We are openness, availability, and communion. Another contribution of Dr. Ezeoba is that he thereby ←x | xi→inaugurates a new group of neo-Thomists. Whereas Clarke and his likes could be regarded as the earlier neo-Thomists, Dr. Ezeoba belongs to the contemporary neo-Thomists. He identifies with the philosophical movement which came to light at the dawn of the twentieth century – philosophy is relevant to life. He is saying precisely that Thomistic thought was not born and buried in the medieval period; it is readable by the contemporary thinker and relevant to him. The Thomistic idea is vital to life.

His work is timely in this era of apparent “blackout” both in religious and social life. Concerning the former, in Europe, it is the presence of myriads of staggering voices on what constitutes authentic Catholic Teaching. There seems to be a war between strict traditionalists and extreme modernists. In many African countries, it is an unpretentious going back to the practice of African Traditional Religion by a number of baptized Christians, especially the young ones. This work can help to steer a middle course – not what I want God to be but to discover what he really is using the views of contemporary neo-Thomistic thinkers. As for the latter, whereas many African countries are still struggling without success to get out of poverty (both of thought and material things), the undoubted economic achievement of Europe and America seem to generate an era of struggle for supper power through the use of modern and dangerous weapons that could possibly but unfortunately lead to a third world war. It follows that there is a global social problem. The starting point towards a resolution is understanding what constitutes authentic development. This work gives us the green light. It begins with the “I” understanding that they are not alone in the world. There is the OTHER (irrespective of the continent of origin) to be appreciated and cherished.

This work is for more than just students of philosophy and professional philosophers. I recommend it to all – both Africans and non-Africans.

Professor Sylvanus Ifeanyichukwu Nnoruka,
Chukwuemeka Odumegwu Ojukwu University, Igbariam Campus,
Nigeria.

←xii | 1→

Introduction

Clarke’s Life

William Norris Clarke was born on June 1, 1915, in New York, United States of America. After graduating from Loyal High School in New York, he enrolled at Georgetown University in 1931. On August 14, 1933, he entered the Society of Jesus Congregation (Jesuit) at St. Andrew-on-Hudson, Poughkeepsie in Maryland, New York Province, at the age of 18.

He developed an interest in Thomism at the College of St. Louis in England in 1936 under the tutelage of André Marc, who was one of the leaders of the French branch of Transcendental Thomism inspired by Joseph Maréchal, S.J. (1878–1944), a Belgian Jesuit priest.1 According to Clarke, Marc’s central ←1 | 2→philosophical vision was the notion of being as an existential act in the thought of St. Thomas Aquinas (1225/7 – 1274 A.D.).2 Clarke later furthered his studies at Fordham University, obtaining a Master’s degree in Philosophy in 1940.3 He was ordained a Catholic priest in the Order of the Society of Jesus in 1945. Between 1947 and 1950, he earned his doctoral degree in Philosophy at the University of Louvain, Belgium, with a dissertation entitled “The principle: ‘Actus non limitatur nisi per potentiam:’ [Acts are not limited except by potency] Its sources and meaning in St. Thomas.”4 After his doctorate, he taught briefly at Woodstock College and Bellarmine College in Plattsburg, New York. In 1955 he joined the faculty of philosophy at the University of Fordham as a lecturer. In 1961 he helped found the International Philosophical Quarterly (IPQ), which promotes philosophy between European and American scholars, and of which he was its Editor-in-Chief from 1961 to 1985. In addition, he was the President of the Metaphysical Society of America, the American Catholic Philosophical Association, the Jesuit Philosophical Association of North America, and the International St. Thomas Society. He received an Honorary Doctor of Law from Villanova University and an Honorary Doctor of Humanities from Wheeling Jesuit College. He also taught in many Jesuit colleges and universities in the United States of America.5 He became an emeritus Professor of philosophy at Fordham University in 1985. He died in Bronx, of a stroke, in June 2008 at 93. According to Koterski and Drummond, Clarke often regarded himself as an Existential Thomist in the tradition of Étienne Gilson. He viewed Thomistic metaphysics as an original ←2 | 3→synthesis of Aristotelianism and Neo-Platonism.6 In his studies and lectures, certain factors influenced him that helped shape his thought on the human person.

Factors That Shaped His Notion of the Human Person

Many of these factors were anticipated by the call to revive Thomism which was ushered in by the encyclical of Pope Leo XIII (1810–1903), Aeterni Patris (1879).7 However, Knasas argues that before the encyclical of Leo XIII, there was a revival of Thomism which started in the Dominican General Chapter in 1838. From this prior revival came the teaching of Thomism by Canon Vincenzo Buzzetti at the Vincentian College in Piacenza, Italy. From there, two disciples of Buzzetti spread the Thomist enthusiasm of their master to Joachim Pecci, who later became Pope Leo XIII.8 Leo’s call prompted decades of Thomistic revival with publications of books, journals, and periodicals that served as a good way to confront the ills of Modernism.9 Clarke later joined in this quest for the revival. He writes that his first exposure to systematic Thomistic metaphysics was during his studies from 1936 to 1939 under a brilliant young French Thomist, André Marc, S.J., which I mentioned above.10 Later he was influenced by the work of the founder of this school of Thomism, Joseph Maréchal, entitled Le Point de Départ de la Métaphysique [The Point of Departure of Metaphysics]. This work was anticipated ←3 | 4→by the L’Action [Action] (1893) of Maurice Blondel (1861–1949), in which Blondel argued that human condition is of necessity to act or an a priori radical dynamism of the will to act. For Blondel, “to be is to will and to love.”11 Hence he seems to have likened being to willing and loving, that is, with action. Transcendental Thomism, which emerged in an effort to reconcile the thought of Aquinas with Cartesian subjectivism and Kantian epistemology, employed more or less this a priori of Blondel.12 Clarke says that such a notion of a priori has a lasting effect on his philosophical vision of the human person.13 Proponents of Transcendental Thomism include Joseph Maréchal (the founder), Karl Rahner (1904–1984), Emeric Coreth, Bernard Lonergan (1904–1984), and Auguste Brunner, S.J. Brunner was one of Clarke’s professors at the Island of Jersey. His work, La personne incarneé [The incarnate Person] (1947), which described linguistic dialogue as the starting point of philosophy, significantly influenced Clarke.14 Another influential factor was the process philosophy of Alfred North Whitehead and his disciple, Charles Hartshorne, who argued that everything is in continuous flux and that God “mutates” with the universe.15 His disciple, Hartshorne, further argued that God constantly changes and grows with the universe.16 Influenced by their thought, Clarke would later argue that the divine simplicity in Aquinas is too rigid. There was also the influence of the school of Existential Thomism with proponents such as Étienne Gilson (1884–1978) and Joseph de Finance, and others such as his two metaphysics professors: Fernand Van Steenberghen and ←4 | 5→Louis De Raeymaeker.17 One central thought of some existential Thomists is that Aquinas’ act of existence or esse is intrinsically dynamic, not static. Clarke says that existential Thomists emphasize the importance of a historical approach to Aquinas and de-emphasize Aquinas’ continuity with Aristotle. Clarke describes his work as leaning more toward this school of Thomism.18 There was also an influence from the well-developed relational notion of the human person by the contemporary existential phenomenologists and also personalists such as psychologists and psychotherapists, which he described as one of the stimuli that motivated his notion of the human person. Contemporary phenomenology and personalism were the offshoots of the existentialism of Søren Aabye Kierkegaard (1813–1855). Phenomenology became popular in the Twentieth century with its founder, Edmund Husserl (1859–1938).19 Other prominent figures include ←5 | 6→Martin Heidegger, Jean-Paul Sartre, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Paul Ricoeur, Emmanuel Levinas, Alfred Schütz, and others.20

Another stimulus for Clarke was the challenge laid down by Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger (a. 1927 -) – Pope Benedict XVI - in which he argued that many ancient thinkers thought that unity (substance) is divine, and plurality (relation) was considered as secondary and a disintegration of unity. But he argues that the Christian doctrine of the Trinity has revealed that divinity lies beyond our category of unity and plurality.21 Ratzinger criticized St. Thomas Aquinas particularly for not utilizing this relational mode, already treated in theology, at the philosophical level.22 In defense of Aquinas, Clarke argued that this notion of relation which is primordial as substance is implicit in the thought of Aquinas and that he wants to make it explicit.23 He admitted, however, that the metaphysical tradition of the ancient and medieval philosophy laid more emphasis on the notion of person as a substance which led to its rejection by some Modern thinkers. In contrast, contemporary philosophy’s phenomenological tradition emphasized the idea of relation more.24

Methodology

To better understand what Clarke meant by his notion of the human person as substance-in-relation, I want first to explain his understanding of substance and then that of relation so that one can easily grasp them.25 So, I divided this ←6 | 7→research into four parts. Part one deals with Clarke’s notion of substance which includes: an analysis of his theory of substance in relation to that of Thomas Aquinas, his discussion on the rejection of substance by Modern thinkers, and the emergence of a new idea of substance. Part two centers on the analysis of his notion of relation, which comprises: a study of his theory of primordial relation vis-à-vis relation in Aquinas’ thought; his explanation of the well-developed idea of relation in contemporary thought. Part three focuses on his view of the human person as substance-in-relation. Here one will see the unification of his notion of substance and relation in the human person. The last part deals with two problems: a. to furnish some elements that will help to evaluate whether Clarke’s notion of the human person as substance-in-relation is more of a “creative retrieval” or more of a “creative completion” of the thought of St. Thomas. b. attempt to highlight the relational problem in his thought. In this last part, I will attempt a proposal on how the relationality that Clarke described as beginning in the first act could be developed to become the primordial relation that is ontologically equal to substance.

Sources

The main works of Clarke from where this research obtained its study of the notion of the human person as substance-in-relation are The Philosophical Approach to God: A Contemporary Neo-Thomist Perspective, in which he presents the unrestrained dynamism of the human spirit and the metaphysical ascent to God;26 Person and Being, where Clarke presents his “creative retrieval and completion” of St. Thomas on the metaphysics of the human person and the contemporary notion of relation;27 Explorations in Metaphysics: Being—God—Person, which is a collection of articles where he deals with the metaphysical notions of being, God and person;28 The creative retrieval of St. Thomas Aquinas: Essay in Thomistic ←7 | 8→philosophy, new and old, which is another collection of articles where he treats a wide range of philosophical topics;29 The One and the Many: A Contemporary Thomistic Metaphysics, in which he retrieved the notion of being as One and many (relational) while reflecting on such topics as existence, truth, change, time, and substance.30 There are other books, numerous articles, edited works of Clarke, and a lot essays and reviews from other authors on him and on substance, relation, and human person from where I will obtain some ideas and critical analysis of Clarke’s notion of the human person. Some works of St. Thomas Aquinas which I utilized in this research include Summa contra Gentiles [Summa against the gentiles], Summa Theologica [Summa theology], Summa Theologiae the metaphysics of Aristotle, Summa Theologiae Aristotle’s Physics, Sentencia libri de anima [On the soul], and others.


1 W. N. Clarke, “Twenty-fourth award of the Aquinas medal, by the American Catholic Philosophical Association, to W. Norris Clarke, S.J.,” in The creative retrieval of St. Thomas Aquinas: Essay in Thomistic philosophy, new and old, Fordham University Press, New York (NY) 2009, 11–12. Neo-Thomism is a term used to describe the revival of St. Thomas Aquinas’ philosophy, which began during the second half of the nineteenth century, especially with the emergence of Leo XIII’s Aeterni Patris [Of the Eternal Father]. Sometimes the word Neo-Scholasticism is also used instead. Cf. J. Knasas, Being and some twentieth-century Thomists, 31–32; W. N. Clarke, “The turn to the inner way in contemporary neo-Thomism,” in The philosophical approach to God: A new Thomistic perspective, Fordham University Press, New York (NY) 2007, 1–2.; E. T. Long, Twentieth-century western philosophy of religion 1900-2000, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht 2003, 337.

2 Idem, Explorations in metaphysics: Being, God, person, University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame (IN) 2008, x. Cf. Idem, “Twenty-fourth award of the Aquinas medal, by the American Catholic Philosophical Association, to W. Norris Clarke, S.J.,” 12.

3 Ibidem, xi.

4 J. W. Koterski and J. J. Drummond, “W. Norris Clarke, S.J., 1915–2008,” in Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 82, 5 (2009), 202. (my translation).

5 Ibidem, 229. Cf. W. N. Clarke, Person and being, Marquette University Press, Milwaukee (WI) 2004, ii.

6 J. W. Koterski and J. J. Drummond, “W. Norris Clarke, S.J., 1915–2008,” 202.

7 Leo XIII, Encyclical letter Aeterni patris [Of the Eternal Father] (4 August 1879), nn. 31, AAS 12 (1879) 97–115.

8 J. Knasas, Being and some twentieth-century Thomists, Fordham University Press, New York (NY) 2003, 31.

9 Many Thomists who embarked on this revival project include Joseph Maréchal, Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange, Étienne Gilson, Jacques Maritain, and many others. Cf. J. Knasas, Being and some twentieth-century Thomists, Fordham University Press, New York (NY) 2003, 31.; G. Gutting, French philosophy in the twentieth century, Cambridge University Press, New York (NY) 2001, 94.; P. Gleason, Contending with modernity: Catholic higher education in the twentieth century, Oxford University Press, New York (NY) 1995, 109ff.

10 W. N. Clarke, Explorations in metaphysics: Being, God, person, xi–xii. Cf. W. N. Clarke, “Twenty-fourth award of the Aquinas medal, by the American Catholic Philosophical Association, to W. Norris Clarke, S.J.,” in The creative retrieval of St. Thomas Aquinas: Essay in Thomistic philosophy, new and old, Fordham University Press, New York (NY) 2009, 11.

11 M. Blondel, L’Action [Action] 1893, Presses Universitaires de France, Paris 20132, Xxiii.

12 There is no denial of the influence of Maurice Blondel on Maréchal’s brand of Thomism. But the fact is that Maréchal may not be regarded as a disciple of Blondel because he regarded Blondel’s work as inclining more toward voluntarism than toward the tenets of Transcendental Thomism. Cf. F. C. Copleston, 19th and 20th century French philosophy, Doubleday, New York (NY) 1994, 268.

Details

Pages
XII, 292
Year
2023
ISBN (PDF)
9781433196492
ISBN (ePUB)
9781433196508
ISBN (Hardcover)
9781433196485
DOI
10.3726/b19603
Language
English
Publication date
2023 (May)
Keywords
consciousness Thomism phenomenology metaphysics Rethinking the Angelic Doctor Substance relation human person community esse agere Norris W. Clarke and the Concept of Person in Thomas Aquinas
Published
New York, Bern, Berlin, Bruxelles, Oxford, Wien, 2023. XII, 292 pp.

Biographical notes

Aloysius N. Ezeoba (Author)

Aloysius N. Ezeoba obtained his PhD in philosophy from the Pontifical Urbaniana University, Rome, Italy. Currently he lectures on metaphysics at Bigard Memorial Seminary, Enugu, Nigeria where he is the Deputy Head of the Philosophy Department.

Previous

Title: Re-thinking the Angelic Doctor
book preview page numper 1
book preview page numper 2
book preview page numper 3
book preview page numper 4
book preview page numper 5
book preview page numper 6
book preview page numper 7
book preview page numper 8
book preview page numper 9
book preview page numper 10
book preview page numper 11
book preview page numper 12
book preview page numper 13
book preview page numper 14
book preview page numper 15
book preview page numper 16
book preview page numper 17
book preview page numper 18
book preview page numper 19
book preview page numper 20
book preview page numper 21
book preview page numper 22
book preview page numper 23
book preview page numper 24
book preview page numper 25
book preview page numper 26
book preview page numper 27
book preview page numper 28
book preview page numper 29
book preview page numper 30
book preview page numper 31
book preview page numper 32
book preview page numper 33
book preview page numper 34
book preview page numper 35
book preview page numper 36
book preview page numper 37
book preview page numper 38
book preview page numper 39
book preview page numper 40
306 pages