Loading...

A Social Onto-Epistemology

by Mariola Kuszyk-Bytniewska (Author)
©2023 Monographs 188 Pages

Summary

Table Of Contents

  • Cover
  • Title
  • Copyright
  • About the author
  • About the book
  • This eBook can be cited
  • Contents
  • Preface
  • Chapter I A Glimpse Backwards – Onto-Epistemological Threads in Social Philosophy
  • 1. The pluralistic model of knowledge and its ontic-ontological motivation: Aristotle
  • 2. The unitary model of knowledge: Descartes
  • 3. Modern sciences versus ancient sciences: Oblivion of the common foundation
  • 4. Theoretical versus practical sciences: The modern detachment of knowledge from action
  • Chapter II Onto-Epistemological Transgression of Epistemocentrism
  • 1. Arbitrary and ideological orders of science: A consequence of the unitary model of knowledge
  • 2. Sociology as a special representative of social sciences
  • 3. Epistemocentrism: An epistemological obstacle and the source of recurrent crises of social theories
  • 4. Truth in social sciences
  • Chapter III A Social Onto-Epistemology
  • 1. Onto-epistemological specificity of social sciences
  • 2. Onto-epistemology of rationality
  • 3. Onto-epistemology of objectivity
  • 4. Onto-epistemology of intersubjectivity
  • Chapter IV Polish Contribution: Ossowski and Znaniecki in View of Social Onto-Epistemology
  • 1. Ossowski’s road to onto-epistemology
  • 2. Znaniecki’s reflexive onto-epistemology
  • Conclusion
  • Bibliography
  • Subject Index
  • Names Index
  • Series Index

←6 | 7→

Preface

This book has an interdisciplinary character. It concerns the border area between philosophy and social sciences, among which sociology occupies a prominent place.

Social onto-epistemology is a polemical answer to classical, traditional divisions within philosophy, which, as the history of philosophy shows, separate ontology from epistemology, alternately giving priority to one or the other. Classical philosophy, rooted in the intellectual impulse of antiquity, gave priority to ontology, while early modern philosophy privileged the theory of cognition. Following the rise of empirical sciences on the human being in the 19th century, sociology, along with other social sciences, got squeezed into the Cartesian paradigm perpetuating the primacy of epistemology as the first philosophy. Even well into the 20th century, the primacy of epistemology was understood quite traditionally: as a privilege of specific, philosophical insight into sciences allowing for their validation. The price to pay for it turned out in the form of “epistemocentrism” and “scholastic ethnocentrism”. This is how Pierre Bourdieu called an approach privileging constrained, scholarly (i.e. created in the scholars’ community) point of view, which dismisses all kinds of reconstructions of practical approach to knowledge, exercised by people investigated by scholars. In “Pascalian Meditations” Bourdieu consciously referred not only to Pascal, but also to Cartesian tradition (Descartes and Husserl). Scholastic, in Bourdieu’s terms, point of view, itself meditatively detached from social life, establishes norms of description. These norms re-evaluate the scholar’s point of view, carrying the intellectual burden of his/her experiences and research practices, and on the other hand, they re-evaluate the priority of epistemology as an area of validating scientific knowledge, an area where standards of scientific knowledge are forged. This state of affairs only perpetuates a certain form of a contradiction within scientific cognition: it is ready to reconstruct practical knowledge, but only by means of scholastic knowledge, inadequate to the subject matter. The theoretical value of Bourdieu’s attacks depends on the fact that he questions the very core of epistemocentric tradition, using resources provided by ←7 | 8→social sciences. Thus epistemocentrism and scholasticism in theories describing social reality become a trap. To use Gaston Bachelard’s terms, it is an “epistemological obstacle” and the source of recurring crises of social theories’ self-awareness.

In my understanding, the cardinal sin of epistemocentrism is overlooking ontic properties of objects investigated by social sciences, namely, that they are social tissue woven by different subjects’ actions. Social actors’ knowledge motivates their actions, but also inevitably takes part in constituting them as subjects.

Onto-epistemological transgression of epistemocentrism in the area of sociology, as I see it, is reaching beyond it for manners of conceptualising social life in categories of objectivity, rationality and intersubjectivity, as both ontological and epistemological qualifications. In my project it entails modifying meanings of these notions to encompass relations between manners of being and constituting subjects with modalities of knowledge and self-knowledge, which the modern and post-modern forms of common, social life environment make foundations of contemporary subjectivity forms. Sociology is a special science, because it produces sure knowledge about its theoretically constituted objects, and, at the same time, it reciprocally changes that knowledge which serves practical constitution of subjects participating in social realities. In other words, sociology is a sort of knowledge that produces certain knowledge of social reality, which, circulating in society, reflexively changes sociology. Sociology, then, in its meta-reflection, reaches for philosophy and thereby lies a problem: a discrepancy between research practice and reflection on it. Philosophical thought on sociology considers knowledge that it provides and strives to place it in a general, broader order of knowledge. But knowledge so severed from the conditions of its production and described in a quasi-objectivist way (modelled on natural sciences) stops making sense. Therefore, since the emergence of the discipline, sociology struggled with its status as knowledge; epistemocentrically oriented philosophical thought on science could not grasp that specificity. Early modern philosophy was not able to recognise the communitarian dimension of sociological and social study, whereas the individualist, Cartesian epistemology was blind to that background.

←8 |
 9→

Shortly, philosophical reflection on social study was one-sided, hence newly born sciences of man (the 19th century), validated with tools of early modern philosophy, were bound for failure. To explain the status and describe the identity of social sciences, not only cognitive involvement of theory is necessary, but also ontic. Hence epistemology and ontology need to be combined in meta-reflection on knowledge about society. On the other hand, social reality is an indispensable component of social study. Nowadays, the concept of creating knowledge independent from human (cultural, social) environment has been largely abandoned, and rightly so. Nobody today believes in pure science, uninvolved, distanced from values and meanings, whether on the side of the subject or the object, thus, from the human world, from culture, even in so-called hard sciences. Hence my proposition is to extend and enrich the notion of cognition, to notice and take into account its part in creating social reality. This proposition is what I call social onto-epistemology. Social onto-epistemology is the unity of ontic determination of social study and epistemic determination of social being. Who is the one who investigates and what/who is investigated? The answer to these questions, inevitable in social life, always influences the process of forging the social world, it shapes social reality.

The critique of the Cartesian idea of subjectivity, the critique of the epistemological relation founding the monadic Cogito’s being, which assumed the form of controversy between traditional philosophy of science and sociology of science and sociology of knowledge (so-called science wars) are this book’s recurring themes. In early modernity, the close ties of social, ethical and political practice with the development of knowledge were deemed an obstacle in perfecting science. The care for method led to the separation of theoretical and practical tasks of science, and to the conclusion that knowledge is a result of the marriage between episteme and techne. This engendered universalism based on the Cartesian belief in one world and one science describing it, a science stemming from the trunk of metaphysics, but gradually eliminated from its area. Kant’s criticism basically closes this process. It caused effects that neither Descartes nor Kant could think of. These results included abandoning the ontic foundation of science, filling the blanks in social sciences with prosthetic naturalistic models, seeking makeshift technologies and their social applications, instrumental understanding of technology and experience. ←9 | 10→This was supported by strong philosophical need for systemic ordering of knowledge, accompanying the process of sciences’ differentiation and their divorces with philosophy. As epistemology was granted primacy to other areas of philosophy and cognition was granted primacy to other areas of subject-shaping human activity, action finally became separated from investigation wherever action was construed as techne, as opposed to praxis.

Therefore, in this book I perform a kind of re-evaluation of social sciences’ self-awareness, leaning above all on Pierre Bourdieu’s and Florian Znaniecki’s concepts, but indirectly also on Norbert Elias, Anthony Giddens and Charles Taylor, along with Stanisław Ossowski, Marek Siemek and Barbara Tuchańska. Analysing models of knowledge, Aristotle’s and Descartes’s, I try to portray how the privileged position of cognition theory in European philosophy was acquired, and what it means for social and ethical knowledge, as well as how ontic moments of cognition became marginalised within this knowledge.

Ancient and early modern sciences grew on the same, however historically differentiated, ground, which is human life environment. Whereas Aristotle’s pluralistic model of knowledge allowed scientific grasp of “things capable of being otherwise”, Descartes’s unitary model didn’t anymore. Within post-Cartesian philosophy this common ground was a priori eliminated as a potential epistemological obstacle invalidating the strategy of philosophical criticism. Knowledge and investigation are thus separated from action, science should be uninvolved, distanced, cleansed of what concerns praxis. In early modernity, poiesis was reduced to techne, and scientific knowledge identified with episteme supported with techne, while praxis was refused a place among sciences.

In the further part of the book, I show the transformation of social thought, whereby basic categories describing social reality (rationality, intersubjectivity, objectivity), morph from epistemological into onto-epistemological concepts. Nevertheless, in the area of social sciences, especially in sociology, a new kind of discourse is still missing, onto-epistemological discourse. Only through such a discourse intersubjectivity can reveal its bond with rationality and objectivity in a way that does not produce obstacles and paradoxes in sociologists’ thinking. Instead of overt or tacit use of the ego cogito figure, it is worthwhile to realise the ontically limited character of human rationality. Then we can reveal ethicality ←10 | 11→(widely understood, in the sense of Greek ethos), which is an indispensable component of intersubjectivity. In this new perspective, we should also describe objectivity as a historical, contingent category of our cognitions and forms of knowledge, a category entangled in changes affecting forms of subjectivity (being a subject). Finally, in onto-epistemological discourse we can describe the basic sense of rationality, hinting that it grasps not only cognitive aspects of subjective reference, but also ontic, existential forms of self-reference.

What is interesting for me is that very co-dependence: creating new, onto-epistemological perspective of social research under the influence of new phenomena in the domain of social realities, which are in turn the object of that research. Just as 19th-century social processes forged sociology seeking a rightful place among other scientific disciplines, the social processes that we are taking part in today, are, in my view, the base for reorientation of social sciences. I agree with Florian Znaniecki (whom I consider a precursor of onto-epistemological research), when he states that social reality always exists as someone’s reality, that is, examining its social aspect we must involve the humanistic coefficient, the fact of (co-)being, (co-)investigation and (co-)action. One cannot produce a reasonable social theory overlooking the fact that social reality is (co-)created and (co-)maintained by social actors, who are not only investigating agents, but above all acting subjects, ontically located in communities, cultures, languages, grosso modo in co-constituting practices.

Details

Pages
188
Year
2023
ISBN (PDF)
9783631899991
ISBN (ePUB)
9783631900000
ISBN (Hardcover)
9783631886984
DOI
10.3726/b20898
Language
English
Publication date
2023 (May)
Published
Berlin, Bern, Bruxelles, New York, Oxford, Warszawa, Wien, 2023. 188 pp.

Biographical notes

Mariola Kuszyk-Bytniewska (Author)

Mariola Kuszyk-Bytniewska is a Habilitated Doctor of Philosophy, an Assistant Professor at the Institute of Philosophy (Maria Curie-Sklodowska University in Lublin). She has a philosophical and sociological educational background. Her area of interest in philosophy concentrates on the Philosophy of Social Sciences, Philosophy of Culture, Social Onto-Epistemology, and Sociology of Knowledge.

Previous

Title: A Social Onto-Epistemology
book preview page numper 1
book preview page numper 2
book preview page numper 3
book preview page numper 4
book preview page numper 5
book preview page numper 6
book preview page numper 7
book preview page numper 8
book preview page numper 9
book preview page numper 10
book preview page numper 11
book preview page numper 12
book preview page numper 13
book preview page numper 14
book preview page numper 15
book preview page numper 16
book preview page numper 17
book preview page numper 18
book preview page numper 19
book preview page numper 20
book preview page numper 21
book preview page numper 22
book preview page numper 23
book preview page numper 24
book preview page numper 25
book preview page numper 26
book preview page numper 27
book preview page numper 28
book preview page numper 29
book preview page numper 30
book preview page numper 31
book preview page numper 32
book preview page numper 33
book preview page numper 34
book preview page numper 35
book preview page numper 36
book preview page numper 37
book preview page numper 38
189 pages