Loading...

Doubtful Fictions

The Scepticism of Humour in the English Literary Canon, 1379–1767

by Selena Özbas (Author)
©2023 Thesis 228 Pages

Summary

This book attempts an innovative exploration of the connection between humour and scepticism in the English literary canon. Defining humour as a capability, or better put, as a dunamis, it looks into its ’energeiac‘ forms of actualisation in the English literary imagination from Chaucer to Sterne. Refraining from attributing an essentialist tone and mode to the theoretical and critical reception of English humour, and also humour in a wider context, it works instead within a literary nominalist framework where it is explored as a literary phenomenon that sides with the living, the multifarious, and the experiential dimensions of human action. In doing so, it develops a broader argument concerning the nominalist overtones of English humour where its prominent scepticism purports an epistemological break with the dominant forces of universalism; an argumentative force which cyclically acquires its tenets from the preliminary discussion that focuses on the dynamicism of humour.

Table Of Contents

  • Cover
  • Title
  • Copyright
  • About the author
  • About the book
  • This eBook can be cited
  • Acknowledgements
  • Preface
  • Table of Contents
  • List of abbreviations
  • Introduction: “What do you find so amusing Democritus?”: Comedy, The English Dunamis, and The Poetics of Sceptical Humour
  • Chapter I: Mindful Mirth: The Onto-Medicinal Origins of Humour and Its Cognitive Afterlives
  • Chapter II: “O Humour, Thou whose Name is known / To Britain’s favor’d Isle alone”: The Matter of L’humour anglais and Sceptic Upheavals
  • Chapter III: “Certaynly We Ben Deceyved!”: Ockhamite Scepticism and Trajectories of Poetic Humour in Chaucer’s House of Fame
  • Chapter IV: “The Blacke Poyson of Suspect”: Hobbesian Transitions in Ben Jonson’s Every Man in His Humour and Every Man out of His Humour
  • Chapter V: Farewell to Reason: Humean Scepticism and the Contingent Humour of Laurence Sterne’s Tristram Shandy
  • Conclusion: Quo Vadis, Humour? On the Sceptical Potential of English Humour and Its Nominalist Frontiers
  • Bibliography

List of abbreviations

CHBJ

The Critical Heritage: Ben Jonson, edited by D.H. Craig. London and New York: 1990.

CHGC

The Critical Heritage: Geoffrey Chaucer, edited by Derek Brewer. 2 vols. London and New York: Routledge, 1978.

CHHW

The Critical Heritage: Horace Walpole, edited by Peter Sabor. London and New York: Routledge, 1999.

CHLS

The Critical Heritage: Laurence Sterne, edited by Alan B. Howes. London and New York: Routledge, 1971.

DK

Hermann Diels und Walther Kranz, Die Fragmente Der Vorsokratiker. Berlin: Weidmannsche Verlagsbuchhandlung, 1960.

EMIH

Every Man in His Humour

EMOH

Every Man out of His Humour

HF

House of Fame

PCG

R. Kassel and C. Austin, eds. Poetae Comici Graeci. 8 vols. Berolini et Novi Eboraci: Walter de Gruyter, 1983.

TS

Tristram Shandy

Introduction: “What do you find so amusing Democritus?”: Comedy, The English Dunamis, and The Poetics of Sceptical Humour

I. (Un)Taming of the Shrew: Humour, Comedy, and the Tragic Discourse

The study of humour is a paradoxical pursuit since the history of humour theory/criticism does not perfectly chime in with the individual history of humour. Better put, the development of humour theory and the development of humour itself serve two discursive ends which paradoxically do not necessarily embrace each other. For, humour theory is frequently promoted as an early modernist invention with a fin de siècle complexion1 and this particular attitude implicitly declares the instrumentalisation of humour as a gorgonically shrewd form of literary expression. In agreement with this particularly modernist emotion, the rhetoric surrounding humour theory largely emanates from the precepts of the institution of criticism of the nineteenth and twentieth century academia which required the intellectual “to perform according to the rigorous rules of scholarship.”2 Emerging as part of a metaphysical agenda which would now open new, mysterious vistas for the willing initiates,”3 it is barely deniable that the tradition of modern humour theory mostly considers humour as an ideological extension of its intuitive politics and in this sense it is no wonder that the early academic critics of the early nineteenth century appear too eager to define humour as an instinctual social corrective, a critical attaché that antagonises the “liberal elites” who “elevated positivism to an unofficial credo.”4 In accordance, humour theory creates its own interpretative repertoire that looks forward to re-negotiating the bio-political status of humour rather than looking into the ontological basis of an eons-old human ability. It in this respect that the fin de siècle intellectual’s prominent sense of ennui, disappointment, and “ineffable élan vital which is accessible only to intuition”5 had planted the seeds of a theoretically programmed attempt to understand the raison d’être of the phenomenon of humour in its philosophical, biological, and literary contexts. With slight or major differences, these theoretical contexts were expanded during the twentieth century by the hand of the semantic turn in linguistics,6 the advances in psychology and anthropology,7 and the cognitive neuroscience of humour which proclaimed the connection between the activities of the cerebral cortex and the human capacity for humour which “involves higher-order thinking, especially seeing things from multiple perspectives.”8 Philosophers of art and language writing in the analytical tradition considered the truth-conditions and the logical asymmetry of humour as well as the overlap between the aesthetic sphere of experience and the cognitive sphere of experience which granted humour “even more cognitive engagement than Kant allows.”9 Recent theoretical studies on humour with a more continental tone and approach tend to re-evaluate it under neo-Kantian terms where humour is “not noumenal but phenomenal, not theological but anthropological, not numinous but simply luminous.”10 However, most of these contemporary contexts appear to reserve the political need for explaining humour as a species of counter-metaphysicality that is apropos of their intellectual predecessors.

It would be utterly unfair to assume that the variety of these early modernist and post-modernist contexts have made little contribution to our understanding of humour. For, although it was not until the early nineteenth century that humour theory has managed to establish itself as a distinct category of interpretation and evaluation in literary aesthetics, the variety of these contexts have had a tremendous impact on our understanding of the socio-political functions of humour. On the other hand, though, these critical approaches mostly miss the vital point that despite its fairly late entrance into the critical imagination, humour emerges as an already autonomous human capacity in recorded human history which cannot be simply predicated of its functions or ideological attributes. For, humour theory as a turn-of-the-century enterprise (and by extension contemporary humour theory, in general) wishes to popularise humour as a favourable form of clairvoyant amusement. Even contemporary humour studies which promote humour as a concept that plays along the lines of irrationality and instinctiveness mostly take this late-nineteenth century attitude for granted without noticing that they mostly leave humour theory ‘humourless’ in the sense that they treat it as an apparatus rather than as a distinct human capability. To a certain extent, even a quick glance at older humour traditions reveal a prejudicial position that is analogous to the modern and contemporary reception of humour. For instance, Socrates’s lack of self-knowledge in Plato’s Philebus offers a study in the laughability of not knowing thyself but humorously propels a violent sense of superiority over the ignorant individual. Horace’s painter who paints a coal-black fish with a human head in Satires attends to the humorous merge of logically irreconcilable physical and mental assets while Immanuel Kant’s notion of logical irreconcilability holds responsible the “strained expectation being suddenly reduced to nothing”11 for the production of humour. Aristotle’s man, on the other hand, rushes for a moment of relaxation in the Nichomachean Ethics,12 while Quintilian’s jokes in Institutes act in the capacity of a relief-bringer which humorously dispel melancholy in the audience, and Anthony Ashley Cooper, 3rd Earl of Shaftesbury accentuates in his Sensus Communis the sense of freedom which entails humour since “the natural free spirits” of human beings will seek for psychological release “if imprisoned and controlled.”13 The entirety of these examples display the fact that the recurring philosophical interest in humour documents our persisting interest in it which has later led to the categorisation of humour’s separate functions as (a) a violent form of expressing superiority, (b) an onto-epistemic expression of the dissonance between object and reality, and (c) as a means of neuro-psychological catharsis. But also, they point at the disparity between the legislative power of the institution of criticism and humour’s humanity.

Without resorting to the comfort of extremist interpretations it should be acknowledged that, to a certain extent, the act of theorising about humour leads to the conceptual confinement of its own subject of study. For, common practices in theory either situate humour as an antidote to positivism or define it as part of human functionality which are altogether meant to define the humour-ness, the essence of humour although humour tends to persistently outshine the doctrinal creed. In connection with that point, it can be construed that this particular conceptual confinement is met by the hierarchical organisational structure of literary genres. For, humour is frequently viewed as a comedic device and the humour critic, whether ancient or modern, does not particularly deliberate a distinction between comedy and humour term-wise. Since it is not necessarily specified as an individual ability, it is only ironical to discover that despite our long-lasting engagement with it, humour still appears to suffer from a theoretical invisibility since theory barely ever asks questions about the separate meaning(s) of humour. It is simply known of its relational relevance to comedy and in some specific cases, to laughter. Theory functionalises humour but also standardises it as a symbiote. By doing so, the canon of literary criticism establishes an unavoidable reciprocity and interdependence between humour and comedy without taking into consideration that a reciprocity of this sort risks creating a conceptual void. As a result, humour’s ontological status remains a mystery at large as it does not seem to be particularly known from its near-synonymy with comedy.

Ideally speaking, since we are faced with the conundrum of trying to find a way out of this oddity, it could have been a better starting point where we would have paid specific attention to humour as a concept that has a literary and culture life of its own as distinct from comedy. By way of doing so, we would avoid the trap of conceptual isonomy and could also respond to the possible meaning(s) of humour rather than its functions and fend off the modernist and postmodernist pressure on humour theory. Ironically enough, however, since the humoristic vision of the comic theorist instinctively assumes an innate parallel between comedy and humour, we would have to address first the taxonomically enigmatic situation of comedy as the lower form of literary genres so as to understand and conceptualise humour as a non-essentially comedic endeavour. Otherwise stated, to free humour of the ideological connotations of this ostensible exchangeability we would still have to counter comedy’s banalisation and trivialisation at the hands of cultural and critical reception. To locate the philosophical coordinates of humour, then, I would like to make an argument in favour of the anti-banality of comedy and, in order to do so, would like to refer to a specific moment in the mid-eighteenth-century which will require us to spend some time on the archaic binary opposition between laughing comedy and mournful tragedy.

On New Year’s Eve, 1769, Horace Walpole wrote to his friend, who happened to be on a diplomatic mission in Italy—reporting on the Stuarts in exile—of the “ominous eggs”14 which the last year has laid. Walpole, a proponent and admirer of William Pitt, 1st Earl of Chatham’s adept oratorical skills which to his thinking echoed “a self-consciously classical manner,”15 expressed a personal resentment of John Wilkes’s egregious libertarianism which temporarily prevailed over Chatham’s nationalistic interests whose political undertones, ironically enough, were considered to be in collision with the excessively coarse manners of the reigning monarch, George II.16 He acknowledges the vigour of the constitution which has been recently put to test by the anonymous Junius’s epistolary attacks and finds comfort in the non-uniqueness of the situation as he illustrates the minutest details of the Távora affair;17 a technique in which he particularly took delight.18 The parallelism between the tumultuous Portuguese court scandal which was not only curiously preceded by the 1755 Lisbon earthquake but also possibly included Sebastião de Melo’s hatred towards the power wielding aristocratic families, and the tempestuous political climate of Hanoverian England which appeared to be under constant literary and political attack, leads him to the following conclusion:

I have often said, and oftener think, that this world is a comedy to those that think, a tragedy to those that feel—a solution of why Democritus laughed and Heraclitus wept.19

Walpole’s observation, at large, is a political pay-off in regard to his socio-cultural milieu since the formal onset of the text suggests a familiar Augustan sentiment in its epistolary realism.20 It could also be considered that the reverberation of the aplomb and panache of Walpole’s wit which often had made himself detested21 presents a largely political case in itself that is devoid of literary interests. In either case, however, the conclusion he reaches seems to have more literary consequences than political ones despite his purely political statement. For, contrary to expectation, it is telling of a literary disposition which takes sides with cerebral gaiety that furloughs the conventional attribute of low ridicule attached to comedy and allocates superfluous emotional distress to tragedy whose nature has been frequently located in the mimetic representation of technically complete and philosophically serious series of action(s). In addition, it adds to this set of literary binaries a philosophical duplexity which hideously insinuates the futility of Heraclitusean tragedy in the face of an ever-developing world, leaving little space for grief and a plenty of space for comedy. In accordance, although Walpole’s observatory remarks do not necessarily aspire to the status of literary theory and there is not any clear evidence that he favours comedy/Democritus over tragedy/Heraclitus, it is interesting to note that even seven years later in another letter addressed to Horace Mann he wrote:

To act with common sense according to the moment, is the best wisdom I know; and the best philosophy, to do one’s duties, take the world as it comes, submit respectfully to one’s lot, bless the goodness that has given so much happiness with it, whatever it is, and despise affectation, which only makes our weakness more contemptible, by showing we know we are not what we wish to appear. Adieu!22

Still, it can be maintained that Walpole’s intellectual capriciousness does not necessarily assign him a missionary role with regards to his employment of a philosophically emblematic dichotomy as analogous to a literary binary. For despite his political tendencies and sagacious formulations, other poets with neoclassical tendencies were not oblivious to the competition between tragedy and comedy nor were they unappreciative of the emblematic relation between these two ancient philosophers. A specific moment in Dryden’s Tenth Satire of Juvenal escalates the force of a preceding argument when the poet refers to the “pair of sages”23 who, to his thinking, pursue the same end by different methods. This particular reference can be taken as a palpable allusion to Dryden’s previous remarks on the rather peculiar points of dissimilitude between tragedy and comedy24 but also it could be considered as an implied comment on Democritus’s belittling laughter in the face of human folly and Heraclitus’s tears in the face of unspeakable crime. Furthermore, the “examiner” poet Matthew Prior summons the mirthful spirits of Democritus and the grief-stricken spirit of Heraclitus to mourn humanity’s “greater crimes”25 while towards the dawn of the nineteenth-century, Henry Kirke White addresses his own unpredictable and indeterminate nature by referring to his daily veering “to all points of the compass” and the “laughing and pleas’d child” inside who could be effortlessly “vex’d to the soul with impertinent tattle.”26 Henry Fielding, on the other hand, in the prologue to his The Author’s Farce considers the possibility of flying from Heraclitus’s “sad rules” as he prefers to think of himself as one “bred in Democritus’s schools.”27 In all four of these historically and textually unique instances, these poets and littérateurs appear to suggest a strict contrast between profane light-heartedness and literary mirth in opposition to philosophical moralism and universal tragicality in an identically Walpolean manner. Practicing ‘poesy’ within their own contemporary frameworks with the intention of referring to an ancient opposition, they emulate and re-popularise an “eternal cleavage” since

they saw in Heraclitus’ tears only a magnified version of the ordinary, average man’s sympathetic response to pain and evil, and in Democritus’ laughter an enlarged facsimile of Everyman’s tendency to be amused at the foolish antics of his fellow men.28

In this respect, the non-uniqueness of Walpole’s disposition seems to account for the late neoclassical (or early Romantic) cognisance of two different ancient metaphysical takes on being and its perception.29 For his literary-philosophical blueprint that reproduces the established rivalry between tragedy and comedy vividly describes why the traditional confrontation between the laughing and the weeping philosopher appears to be a prevalent intellectual tactic among eighteenth-century poets who seem to be in favour of taxonomical solidarity over inter-categorical vitality by eventually seeking for a cantankerous division between tragedy and comedy. Correspondingly, it appears that Walpole puts so much effort into remaining neutral throughout the rest of the letter and yet eventually he seems to be enraptured by the allure of Democritean joy since the textual evidence becomes growingly suggestive of his literary and intellectual preferences. It is against this backdrop that looking back on his former correspondence, our suspicions appear to gain more ground since in a much earlier letter to George Montagu, 4th Duke of Manchester in 1761 he does not shy away from signing his letter as Democritus when he writes:

Well! how comfortable it will be tomorrow, to see my perroquet, to play at loo, and not to be obliged to talk seriously—the Heraclitus of the beginning of this letter, will be overjoyed on finishing it to sign himself. Your old friend, DEMOCRITUS.30

Given Walpole’s penchant for the laughing philosopher, a few particular points still remain unexplained. For instance, does Walpole genuinely wish to put to test the vernacularity of comedy against the decency of tragic discourse by insinuating an Aristotelian point of departure or does he, in fact, perceive Democritean comedy as an asset belonging with the cognitive faculties of the human mind contrary to traditional expectation?31 Most important of all, how could it be that the world is a comedy to those who engage in intellectual enquiry when “we should hesitate before clamouring to live in a non-tragic society, since it may have discarded its sense of the tragic along with its sense of value”?32

Regardless of the conscious or unconscious effort put into it, Walpole’s statement and the tone of his letters uniquely put forward the idea that (1) judging from the contrast between literary and philosophical opposites, the history of humankind stands before the careful observer as an open field of boundless probabilities “showing the various ways in which men can contrive to be fools and knaves”33 while more importantly, in our present comedic context, (2) it unfolds a common-sensical and cognitive approach towards worldly affairs that appears to stand as an excellent complement to Democritean comedy. Thus, by favouring comedy over tragedy, Walpole’s referential repertoire emerges as a bona fide interest in taking the world “as it comes” and cutting down on the insincerities which render human beings frail. He sides with Democritean comedy as a rational and cognisant take on the condition of human beings as opposed to the maudlin sentimentality of the tragic discourse. Thus, his uniqueness lies in the fact that his emphatic remark about the cognitive value of comedy, compared to his intellectual forerunners and contemporary comedic commentators and his positioning of Democritean comedy as a force of human reason that is quite unlike the ethereal sublimity of tragedy, seems to hide a far superior critique of the mostly overlooked powers of comedy. In the end, it could be assumed that he invites his eighteenth-century recipient and contemporary reader to spend some time on the following questions: how is it that Heraclitusean tragedy has been considered a far more superior literary engagement which inspired Walpole to write in defence of comedy as a highbrow literary activity? Or even better, what is it that Democritus finds so ‘thoughtfully’ amusing which compellingly forces us to reconsider and re-evaluate the literary and philosophical value of comedy?

Any hasty answer which I might try to give here to either of these questions will be to draw a sweeping conclusion. Instead, we can hope to find some answers by going back to the ancient roots of comedy. For, a remarkable explanation remains unfolded in Timocles’s fourth-century Women Celebrating Dionysia that appears to contain the answers for both questions evoked by Walpole’s remarks. The play captures both the late classical audience’s response to tragic drama which turned out to last longer than they could have ever imagined and makes a compelling case for the educative value of the genre and the virtue of suffering. In this context, it reflects on the belittlement of daily, temporary suffering in contrast with universal human suffering which eventually appears to allow a re-examination of one’s own life.34 This particular re-examination of Timocles’s is broached as cathartic in essence with certain ethical implications that resonate with Aristotle’s eudaimonian approach to good human life. In this particular sense, Timocles recognises the fact that indulgence in an emotional osmosis allows the tragic audience to be “led away from the excesses of his self-absorption in his own narrower experiences of suffering or sorrow to be more engaged in those of others.”35 The speaker, thus, comments on the sorrowful nature of humankind:

Listen, good sir, and see if I speak the truth.

Man is by nature a creature born to suffer,

Details

Pages
228
Year
2023
ISBN (PDF)
9783631904749
ISBN (ePUB)
9783631904756
ISBN (Hardcover)
9783631901243
DOI
10.3726/b20986
Language
English
Publication date
2023 (July)
Keywords
Humour and scepticism English humour Dynamicism of humour
Published
Berlin, Bern, Bruxelles, New York, Oxford, Warszawa, Wien, 2023. 228 pp., 1 fig. b/w.

Biographical notes

Selena Özbas (Author)

Selena Ozbas is an Assistant Professor of English at Istanbul Yeni Yuzyil University, Turkey. Her primary research interests include humour studies and cognitive literary studies with a special focus on late medieval to mid eighteenth-century English literature.

Previous

Title: Doubtful Fictions
book preview page numper 1
book preview page numper 2
book preview page numper 3
book preview page numper 4
book preview page numper 5
book preview page numper 6
book preview page numper 7
book preview page numper 8
book preview page numper 9
book preview page numper 10
book preview page numper 11
book preview page numper 12
book preview page numper 13
book preview page numper 14
book preview page numper 15
book preview page numper 16
book preview page numper 17
book preview page numper 18
book preview page numper 19
book preview page numper 20
book preview page numper 21
book preview page numper 22
book preview page numper 23
book preview page numper 24
book preview page numper 25
book preview page numper 26
book preview page numper 27
book preview page numper 28
book preview page numper 29
book preview page numper 30
book preview page numper 31
book preview page numper 32
book preview page numper 33
book preview page numper 34
book preview page numper 35
book preview page numper 36
book preview page numper 37
book preview page numper 38
book preview page numper 39
book preview page numper 40
230 pages